Okay, entanglement and spooky action at a distance. Let me give you my version of the best way to think about it. One's mileage, as ever, is permitted to vary. (1/n)
The fundamental idea is that we shouldn't think of "two separate particles" as two separate particles. They are just one thing. But in a precise way that departs from our classical intuition. (2/n)
Say we have two spinning electrons. Four important things about quantum mechanics: (1) When we *measure* the spin of one particle, we will only get "up" or "down" with respect to our chosen axis, never something in between. (3/n)
(2) When we're not measuring, the spin can be a superposition of both up and down. (3) On the basis of the particular superposition it is in, we can predict the probability of a measurement outcome, but can't be certain. (4/n)
(4) Two particles may be (don't have to be) entangled: we don't know what answer we'll get if we measure either spin, but if we measure one we can instantly be 100% confident what the other will be, even if it's light-years away. (5/n)
What's up with that? How do they know? (6/n)
The formalism of quantum mechanics is perfectly clear about the answer, but sometimes it's hard to face up to it.
We are attached to our observations, and are reluctant to admit a gap between them and the underlying reality. (7/n)
We describe the two particles using a wave function, or "quantum state." It's a *single* wave function, even if it's two particles. Or any other number of particles. Just one wave function, not a separate one for each particle. (8/n)
So: there aren't two separate things. There is just one thing - the quantum state - with two parts to it.
So of course the measurement outcomes will be related. We're measuring different aspects of the same thing. (9/n)
The mystery is not "how can these outcomes be correlated even though they're far away?", it's "why is it ever useful to think of different parts of the wave function as representing `things far away from each other'?" (10/n)
I.e., there's not just a little bit of non-locality we have to learn to live with. QM is by its nature entirely, hilariously non-local - or "alocal," even better. Why are we so tempted by locality at all?
This question has an easy aspect and a hard one. (11/n)
Easy aspect: In the real world, the way that quantum states evolve is naturally thought of in terms of local variables. Particles have positions, fields have values at points in space. Those give very convenient ways of representing the quantum state. (12/n)
Almost too convenient. There are "no-signaling" theorems that say we cannot use quantum entanglement to send information faster than light. These theorems depend on the *specific* way that quantum states evolve -- the "laws of physics." (13/n)
Hard aspect: Why do the laws of physics take just the right form so as to allow us to describe the world (approximately, but really really well) in terms of stuff happening at "points in space"? (14/n)
Hope you don't expect me to answer that one. We don't know, but some of us have ideas! Science isn't finished yet, but we're working on it. Stay tuned. (15/15)
• • •
Missing some Tweet in this thread? You can try to
force a refresh
When talking about many-worlds quantum mechanics, I struggle with answering "Where does the energy come from to make extra worlds?" If you know the equations there's no worry -- energy is perfectly conserved. But it's hard to explain in words. So here is my latest attempt! (1/n)
The basic point is this: there is a crucial difference between "the energy of the whole set of worlds" and "the energy you measure from within any world." Call them the "overall energy" and the "in-world energy." The overall energy is clearly, unambiguously constant. (2/n)
As the wave function of the universe branches, the number of worlds increases. The overall energy is constant because the contribution from each individual world goes down -- worlds become "skinnier." But you don't perceive any such thing from within a world. (3/n)
It was early 2019 when I did this podcast interview about the fall of the Roman Republic, with historian Edward Watts. Well before the Jan. 6 2021 attach on the US Capitol. But the parallels are pretty hard to miss. preposterousuniverse.com/podcast/2019/0…
The Roman Republic had lasted for 500 years, and seemed invincible. But things had become a little ossified. Inequality grew. Tiberius Gracchus was an establishment politician whose career was faltering, so he pivoted to populism. Give land to the peasants.
Fine, as far as that goes. But he was stymied by opposition forces. So he decides to manifest the will of the people: bringing a mob of supporters to depose politicians who opposed him. Not a violent mob, but an intimidating one. The strategy worked.
Anti-free-will people have to stop leaning on determinism. It's perhaps the most wrong that an argument can be.
1) The world is not deterministic. Quantum mechanics exists. When there is hidden determinism (MWI, Bohm), it's hidden! Irrelevant to what people experience. (1/n)
Determinism can be a good approximation for macroscopic dynamics sometimes. So what? Sometimes it's not. You don't want to base arguments about something as fundamental as free will or its absence on a principle that is just a good approximation sometimes. (2/n)
2) The question of whether the laws of nature are deterministic is utterly irrelevant to the question of whether there is libertarian free will. All that matters is whether there are laws. Stochastic laws don't allow for free will any more than deterministic ones do. (3/n)
Everything Everywhere All at Once is Daniels' new film, starring the amazing Michelle Yeoh. See it if you haven't already: endlessly inventive, provocative, and warmly human. a24films.com/films/everythi…
Brad provides an excuse to mention something interesting about quantum mechanics: why we observe some things and not others. I suspect even Sydney (my brilliant former teacher) didn't know the complete answer, since it's not completely known! And he doesn't mention decoherence.
When you set up Schrödinger's Cat to be in a superposition of awake & asleep, then open the box, the miracle of quantum measurement is that you never *see* the cat in such a superposition. You only see definitely awake or definitely asleep. Why?
There are two levels of mystery here!
First level: why do you see something other than the original superposition? That's the quantum measurement problem, very interesting but let's move on to the second level.
A good year for #MindscapePodcast! Here's a list of the topics covered in case you missed any.
128 Western psychology
129 Democracy threatened
130 Fundamental physics
131 Alien artifacts
132 Growth and form
133 Invisible realities
134 Behavior and the mind
135 Plato in China
136 Cyberspace sociology
137 Foundations of math
138 Sports analytics
139 Equality and ideology
140 Neuroscience of time
141 Networks and attention
142 Writing stories
143 Bias and rationality
144 Particle physics
145 History and catastrophes
146 Topology and category theory
147 Cuisine and empire
148 Democracy and problem-solving
149 Time and reality
150 Explanations
151 Mathematics of gerrymandering
152 Criminology and incarceration
153 Quantum computers
154 Religion and meaning
155 Hypergraph physics
156 Data feminism