An illiberal riding the tiger. Writer & Translator.
https://t.co/ZHLU66URd1
19 subscribers
Oct 6 • 4 tweets • 7 min read
1/ America lives under two rival and irreconcilable constitutions: the original, and the one imposed by force through the Civil Rights Act of 1964.
The postwar order rested upon an illusion of continuity, a dream of permanence concealing the slow decay of the Republic beneath it. Beneath the surface of prosperity and the rhetoric of liberty, the foundations of the old order had already begun to crumble.
What Christopher Caldwell accomplishes in The Age of Entitlement: America Since the Sixties is not merely to trace this decline but to reveal the mechanism by which it occurred. Written with the restraint of a man long accustomed to respectable discourse, the book nonetheless advances one of the most subversive theses to appear from the American Right in half a century: that the Civil Rights Act of 1964 created a second constitution, a rival order of law and morality, and that this new constitution has displaced the old in practice, leaving behind only the symbols and ceremonies of the former Republic.
Caldwell is no pamphleteer. A veteran of The Weekly Standard and a contributor to The New York Times, he occupies that peculiar place in American letters reserved for men who think carefully yet are punished for seeing too clearly. It was inevitable, therefore, that his book would be met with hysteria. The New York Times called it “an overwrought and strangely airless book” that “leads nowhere.” The Washington Examiner dismissed it as “Trumpism for highbrows.” Yet such reactions reveal less about Caldwell than about the clerisy he exposes. The fury of his reviewers testifies to the truth of his insight; he has touched the sacred nerve of the modern order, the moral absolutism of civil rights, which polite society forbids anyone to question.2/ In its surface structure, The Age of Entitlement is a history of America from the assassination of John F. Kennedy to the rise of Donald Trump. But beneath its chronology lies a moral and constitutional argument of far greater consequence. Caldwell shows how the civil rights movement, ostensibly a campaign for racial equality, became the model for an entirely new form of governance in which law is subordinate to moral feeling and the state exists to enforce a vision of universal redemption. What began as an appeal to conscience was institutionalized as a bureaucracy of coercion. Out of the ruins of segregation arose a new elite of administrators, judges, and corporate patrons who discovered that the rhetoric of justice could serve as the instrument of power.
Caldwell’s claim that the Civil Rights Act became a Second Constitution was not metaphorical. The law was drafted as a limited measure; its framers promised it would not create quotas or destroy private association. Yet once enacted, it expanded without limit, its implications treated by the courts with the same reverence once reserved for the Bill of Rights. Through the Civil Rights Act, federal authority extended into every sphere of private life, reaching from employment and education to housing, speech, and even thought, until it became impossible to act freely without transgressing the new moral code. What was once the liberty of the citizen became the privilege of the compliant. The old constitution, with its balance of powers and jealous regard for local autonomy, was hollowed out from within by a rival order of legislation, precedent, and bureaucratic fiat.
This development, Caldwell observes, was not the product of a sudden coup but of moral transformation. The Civil Rights Act fused law and religion, replacing the Constitution’s procedural neutrality with a creed of emotional righteousness. To oppose its expansion was to sin. In this sense, the regime it founded was theological rather than legal; its authority derived not from consent but from sanctity. The language of rights replaced the language of reason, and the courts came to interpret feeling as fact. The civil rights order became a form of political mysticism, an instrument of redemption that demands endless confession and sacrifice.
Sep 30 • 5 tweets • 7 min read
1/ On April 24, 1916, while the Great War consumed the continent and the empires of Europe strained beneath the weight of modern industrial slaughter, a handful of Irish rebels seized the heart of Dublin and proclaimed the birth of a Republic.
They occupied the General Post Office, raised their flag above Sackville Street, and read aloud a proclamation in the name of God and the dead generations. To outside observers it appeared a futile gesture: scarcely a thousand men, armed with little more than rifles and shotguns, defying the garrison of the British Empire. Yet in that week of fire and ruin the Irish question ceased to be a matter of parliamentary negotiation and became instead a struggle of destiny.
Patrick Pearse, the poet and schoolmaster who stood at the head of the Volunteers, did not expect victory in arms. He sought to enact a myth, to consecrate the Republic in blood. His conviction resembled what Georges Sorel was then formulating in France: that nations are not held together by rational programs or parliamentary bargains, but by myths that grip the soul and sanctify sacrifice.
For Pearse, that myth was Ireland redeemed through martyrdom, a fusion of Christian passion with the pagan heroic temper of Cú Chulainn. He knew that he and his comrades would be crushed, and that many of their own people would revile them for the devastation of Dublin. Yet he believed their deaths would awaken the nation, and that from their graves a people would rise, determined never again to live as subjects.2/ The Rising lasted six days. The Volunteers and members of the Irish Citizen Army held public buildings across Dublin, but artillery and gunfire soon reduced them to ruins. Civilian casualties mounted into the hundreds, and public opinion turned against the insurgents. On April 29 Pearse surrendered. He and the other leaders were court-martialed and executed in early May, among them James Connolly, already so badly wounded that he had to be tied to a chair before the firing squad. At first the people of Dublin spat upon the defeated Volunteers. Yet as the executions followed one after another, and as British guns shelled the city as though it were an enemy capital, sympathy shifted. The men once denounced as criminals became martyrs, and their deaths gave life to a Republic that had not yet existed in fact.
This was Pearse’s design. He had long believed that Ireland could be reborn only through sacrifice, that the blood of patriots would cleanse and sanctify the nation. His imagination was nourished by the sagas of the Gaels, above all the figure of Cú Chulainn, who stood alone against overwhelming odds and died young in battle. Pearse fused that heroic image with the Christian symbolism of martyrdom, seeing in both the same redemptive power: the death of a few to redeem the many. The Rising was less a military plan than a ritual act, a mythic proclamation through suffering.
The conviction that sacrifice could regenerate a people was not confined to Ireland. Across Europe, men such as Charles Péguy and the Futurists spoke of death in battle as the price of renewal, a cleansing fire against the decadence of liberal society. Pearse stood in this same current, though his expression was Irish, a union of legend and Passion, Cú Chulainn bound to his pillar and Christ upon the cross, each a figure of death that gives life to the nation. His words at his court-martial made the point plain: “We seem to have lost. We have not lost. To refuse to fight would have been to lose. We have kept faith with the past, and handed down a tradition to the future.”
Sep 25 • 5 tweets • 7 min read
1/ The greatest question before the West today is not one of markets or diplomacy but of life itself. Our peoples are dying, not metaphorically but literally, in the most direct biological sense.
Fertility has fallen below the level of replacement, while foreign populations continue to increase. Two processes converge: the inflow of millions of migrants from alien lands and the refusal of Westerners to reproduce themselves. Territory is finite. Employment is finite.
Housing, schools, hospitals, and public revenues are finite. When these resources are consumed by strangers, they are denied to our own descendants. Migrants arrive from poor and overpopulated countries and encounter our labor markets and welfare systems as a sudden wealth. They raise more children here than they could have supported in their homelands.
Across the West, their fertility is consistently higher than ours. Even if borders were sealed tomorrow, the replacement of the native population would continue through differential birthrates. Restriction is not enough. Repatriation is a necessity.2/ Yet immigration, though decisive, is not the whole cause of our crisis. We must face the harder truth that much of our demographic decline arises from within. Fertility among Western peoples fell before mass migration became overwhelming. The sickness is internal. To understand it, we must return to the origins of our social order.
When our ancestors entered the forests and plains of Europe more than forty millennia ago, they faced winters of hunger, scarcity, and cold. Intelligence, foresight, and restraint were forged by this climate. Yet no less important was the dependence of women upon male provision. Unlike in tropical Africa, where women could cultivate the soil with simple hand tools and feed themselves, the West demanded the plough, a labor requiring the full strength of the male body.
Men labored in the fields, women tended the home. Out of this necessity came monogamy, the durable bond between husband and wife, and the elevation of the provider as the true mark of manhood. Across thirteen hundred generations, women developed a preference for capable providers, and men found dignity in fulfilling that role. This was no social convention but an adaptation fixed by time and selection. It cannot be wished away.
Here lies one of the fatal illusions of the modern world. Men believe women should love them “for richer or poorer.” Women believe they desire equality. Yet biology has its own commands. Women will seek provision as instinctively as men seek youth and beauty. To deny this is to deny reality. Feminism, by granting women economic independence, severed this ancient bond.
For the small number of women indifferent to marriage and family, independence may have proved advantageous. For the vast majority, it has been disastrous. Women’s entry into the workforce has depressed male wages and simultaneously raised women’s expectations of what a worthy provider must earn. The result is double pressure upon men: diminished capacity to provide and heightened standards to meet. This is the paradox of modern prosperity: never have material resources been greater, yet never have women been more dissatisfied with men.
Sep 20 • 6 tweets • 8 min read
1/ Carl Schmitt stands as one of the few jurists of the twentieth century who grasped that law and politics cannot be separated, that every constitution rests finally on power and decision, not on procedure or neutral principle. Against the illusions of liberalism, which imagine that societies can be governed through rules, balances, and endless discussion, Schmitt insisted that sovereignty is revealed only at the point of rupture, when order is threatened and authority must act without mediation. He called this the state of exception, the moment when the sovereign decides not within the law but over it, and thereby discloses the true foundations of political order.
For Schmitt, liberalism’s dream of a politics reduced to administration was nothing but a form of decay. Parliamentary systems spoke endlessly of rights, freedoms, and humanity, yet in practice they neutralized the state’s capacity to defend the people. By displacing real decisions into endless procedures, they confused weakness for virtue, compromise for wisdom. Schmitt’s diagnosis was not the rant of a reactionary nostalgic for monarchy, nor the fantasy of a utopian revolutionary. It was the sober recognition that politics, in its essence, is conflict, and that no society can endure if it refuses to recognize its enemies, internal or external, and to affirm its own unity against them.
What, then, can we learn from Schmitt? His writings do not hand down a ready-made program, but they reveal truths about political life that no society can escape. They remind us that politics is never settled, that sovereignty cannot be hidden behind procedures, and that a people survives only by affirming itself against those who would undo it.2/ Schmitt’s first lesson is that conflict cannot be abolished. In “The Concept of the Political” he argued that political life arises from the distinction between friend and enemy, from the ability of a people to recognize those who threaten its existence and to affirm its own being against them. He did not glorify violence, nor did he celebrate war as a positive ideal. His point was sharper: that enmity is a permanent possibility, an irreducible horizon of collective life. No matter how refined institutions become, no matter how elaborate treaties appear, human groups will always find differences they regard as worth defending with their lives. Order itself rests upon acknowledging this fact, for to deny it is to prepare the ground for collapse.
Liberalism denies the permanence of enmity. It dreams of a politics reduced to dialogue, negotiation, and exchange, where all disagreements can be settled by reason or dissolved into tolerance. In practice, this vision erodes the state’s ability to act. A people that refuses to draw boundaries soon discovers that it cannot command loyalty or inspire sacrifice. Where every distinction is blurred, there is nothing left to defend. Such a community is defenseless even against ordinary trials and shatters altogether in moments of crisis. Schmitt’s warning was that politics does not wither away with progress. It endures as long as peoples endure, and when it is forgotten, it returns with greater violence.
Sep 19 • 5 tweets • 5 min read
1/ President Trump is expected to sign the American Tech Workforce Act, the most serious effort yet to defend American technology workers from foreign labor schemes.
It sets a $150,000 minimum salary for H-1B workers, indexed annually, ends the random visa lottery by prioritizing higher pay, and abolishes Optional Practical Training (OPT), the back-door pipeline that corporations and universities use to flood the market with cheap labor.
The message is unmistakable: foreign labor will no longer be subsidized at America’s expense.
It is also one step closer to breaking the Indian ethnic mafia that has entrenched itself in American tech, and elsewhere.
One of the most admirable aspects of tariff policy is how it puts American producers before American consumers. With tariffs in place, prices may rise, but domestic industries survive.
This is a conscious choice to protect American workers from foreign competition, and it works. Tariffs now defend steel and auto jobs, keeping Americans employed rather than consigned to welfare rolls.
The same principle must apply to the technology sector. 2/ The Act raises the wage floor for H-1B workers to $150,000, stripping away the incentive for corporations to import foreigners at half the cost of Americans. Either companies pay the higher wage and prove these workers are truly exceptional, or they hire Americans at a fair market rate.
Yet even with these reforms, the deeper problem must be understood. The H-1B visa was created in 1990 as a temporary work permit for “specialty occupations” that supposedly required foreign talent. In practice, it became a corporate device for importing cheaper labor. Companies claimed they could not find enough American workers, then filled their ranks with foreigners at cut-rate salaries. Up to 85,000 new visas are issued each year, with hundreds of thousands already in the system. Workers are chosen not for excellence but by lottery, a bureaucratic mechanism that has nothing to do with merit.
Sep 15 • 9 tweets • 8 min read
1/ Every political order must answer the oldest question of all: how to restrain the conflict between the few and the many.
Patrick Deneen has become one of the most prominent mainstream critics of the liberal order. His widely discussed book “Why Liberalism Failed” contrasted the promises of the tradition with the evident decay of our present.
His more recent “Regime Change: Toward a Postliberal Future” advances the argument by proposing remedies, with particular emphasis on the recovery of the mixed constitution, an ancient device for reconciling classes and preserving civic stability.2/ Deneen situates his argument within a much older problem, one that the Greeks themselves faced. Their cities were repeatedly consumed by class struggle, oligarchs contending with democrats, at times resorting to the annihilation of rivals. From such experience came the first attempts to understand politics as the art of restraining conflict by cultivating the virtues of each class while suppressing their vices.
The wealthy enjoyed refinement and leisure, yet often succumbed to arrogance and selfishness. The poor, hardened by necessity, lived with frugality and endurance, yet remained vulnerable to envy and demagoguery. Aristotle, Polybius, and others proposed the mixed constitution as the answer: a structure balancing these forces, or a broad middle element capable of stabilizing extremes.
Sep 13 • 6 tweets • 8 min read
1/ No other delusion has been so quickly enthroned as law and creed as transgenderism.
It is not a private sickness to be met with compassion but a public dogma imposed with severity. The mutilation of healthy bodies is paraded as courage, the sterilization of children is praised as liberation, and the corruption of language is enforced as truth.
What was once regarded as disorder is now displayed as identity. What was once concealed in shame is now celebrated openly.
In many districts, schools present fantasy as fact and compel teachers to affirm it. Corporations elevate it in their advertising campaigns and enforce it through internal quotas and mandatory trainings. Governments encode it into civil rights law as if delusion could be legislated into reality.
Those who refuse to comply are punished, stripped of position, or branded with accusations of hatred for speaking the most elementary truths.
The phenomenon reveals more than the suffering of those afflicted. It exposes a civilization that has abandoned the ability to distinguish between compassion and cruelty, between truth and falsehood, between health and mutilation.
What spreads before us is not healing but the enthronement of delusion, not tolerance but the organized machinery of decline.
Let us discuss this insanity.2/ The first evidence of this madness is found in the most basic truths of biology. A man cannot become a woman, nor a woman a man. Chromosomes remain immutable, XY for the male and XX for the female. Hormonal manipulation does not rewrite the code of life, nor can surgery replace the natural form with its opposite.
A mastectomy, the surgical removal of healthy breasts, does not create masculinity but only disfigures a woman. The excision of ovaries halts the natural cycles that regulate fertility and hormonal balance, leaving behind sterility and premature decay.
The mutilation of genitals, whether by constructing a crude imitation of male organs or by fashioning a false cavity in place of the male member, produces wounds that never fully heal and lifelong medical complications. The ingestion of exogenous hormones, designed to mimic secondary sexual traits, may alter voice, skin, or body fat distribution, but only at the cost of liver strain, bone fragility, cardiovascular risk, and permanent dependency upon chemical intervention.
In every case, what is destroyed is real, what is created is counterfeit, and the body is left in a state of ruin. Every cell continues to testify to the sex inscribed at conception, a truth that no scalpel or drug can erase.
The reality is simple: transition is a fraud. It is a counterfeit process that can only destroy, never create. A woman who cuts away her breasts and poisons her body with testosterone does not become a man but only a broken woman. A man who removes his genitals to construct a false organ does not become a woman but only a mutilated man.
What results is not transformation but ruin, and the evidence is written not only on the body but in the permanent sterility, disfigurement, and medical dependence that follow.
Sep 11 • 6 tweets • 8 min read
1/ Weimar Problems Require Weimar Solutions
We have all heard this phrase, yet the chaos and turmoil of our own time now give it a sharper and more unsettling meaning. What once sounded like rhetorical exaggeration has become the daily condition of American life.
Rising crime corrodes the fabric of order, hyper-political partisanship has become a contest of mutual destruction, and White America finds itself increasingly grouped together as the common enemy of every faction. The government, the media, activist lobbies, and minority blocs converge in their hostility, ensuring that the boundary between civic debate and physical violence grows ever thinner. The casual brutality of everyday life now bleeds into the political realm. The horrific murder of Iryna Zarutska aboard a Charlotte light-rail train lays bare the lawlessness that now consumes even mundane public spaces.
In contrast, the assassination of Charlie Kirk, an explicit strike against a public figure, demonstrates that political violence has likewise reentered the sphere of possibility. These events are not isolated anomalies but symptomatic of an urgent, escalating condition. What once seemed unimaginable in a stable Western society is now our reality.
This was the lesson of Weimar: when the state refused to act, chaos spread unchecked, and into that void the Freikorps arose. If America’s leaders remain paralyzed, the same outcome awaits us. And perhaps that is no cause for despair. Better that men step forward to defend what the state will not, than to watch a nation dissolve without resistance.2/ History does not repeat itself in the same form, yet it does return in cycles, presenting the same crises beneath new appearances. The comparison between America and Weimar is therefore not about tracing replicas but about recognizing recurring patterns. The fractures of legitimacy, the collapse of confidence, the descent of politics into open struggle are not unique to Germany after the Great War. They reappear wherever a people, and thus a civilization, has lost faith in its continuity. The names change, the costumes change, but the underlying drama is the same.
The Weimar Republic itself was born out of military defeat and revolutionary upheaval. From its first days it was besieged by violence, and that violence began with the Left. The Spartacist revolt in Berlin, followed by a wave of communist uprisings across German cities, brought chaos to the streets and set the pattern for years of turmoil. The central government stood paralyzed, unwilling to act decisively, unwilling to defend its own people. Out of that paralysis the Freikorps arose, hardened men from the trenches who refused to watch their nation collapse without resistance. They were not an accident of history but its necessity, for when authority abdicates, others must fill the void.
Sep 7 • 6 tweets • 3 min read
1/ In his “Politics,” Aristotle warns that extreme democracy collapses into tyranny. Both rest on flattery and rule by the weakest, upheld by women and slaves, while tyranny above all depends on foreigners, since citizens despise it. 2/ Women and slaves, he writes, “delight in being flattered.” They welcome rulers who indulge them, where law is lax, discipline is weak, and authority bends to those who by nature should be ruled rather than ruling.
Sep 7 • 4 tweets • 11 min read
1/ Let us discuss Plato’s “Timaeus,” the dialogue in which philosophy first dares to speak of the origin of the cosmos.
Of all the dialogues, the “Timaeus” is at once the most audacious in scope and the most far-reaching in its impact. Composed in the fourth century before Christ, it dares to recount nothing less than the origin of the universe, the constitution of the soul, and the place of man within the whole. Where most dialogues proceed through the familiar contest of questions and answers, this work takes the form of a vast monologue, delivered chiefly by the Pythagorean Timaeus of Locri, whose authority rests upon his knowledge of mathematics, astronomy, and cosmology. The “Timaeus” treats creation not as accident or blind motion but as the product of reason. The universe, Plato tells us, is the handiwork of a divine craftsman, the Demiurge, who looks to the changeless order of the eternal forms and, by imitating them, imposes proportion, harmony, and measure upon primordial chaos. In this act philosophy gives to the West its first systematic cosmology, an account that links the visible order of nature to the invisible order of intellect.
For centuries this was the Platonic dialogue par excellence in the Latin West. Cicero translated a portion in the last years of the Republic, and Calcidius in the fourth century supplied a fuller Latin version that remained for nearly a millennium the only substantial access to Plato available to Christian Europe. It was through this channel that the Church Fathers first encountered Plato, and through it that much of Christian theology absorbed the Platonic division of soul and body, the vision of the cosmos as rationally ordered, and the very notion of creation as a purposive act. Yet the historical weight of its influence must not obscure its radical originality. The “Timaeus” is not revelation but philosophy: an attempt by unaided reason to explain why the world exhibits harmony, why the heavens move with regularity, and why the human soul, though exiled in flesh, still recognizes in that celestial order the pattern of its own lost perfection.
To take up this dialogue with understanding is to step into the very beginning of Western thought. Here we are asked why being is superior to becoming, why the soul must rule over the body, and why intellect, never satisfied with mere appearances, strains toward the eternal forms that give structure to all things. The account offered is neither myth in the simple sense nor science as later ages would define it. Though it speaks of triangles, solids, and elements, and though it recounts the sinking of Atlantis and the succession of cosmic cataclysms, it moves on a higher plane. It is what Plato himself calls a eikôs muthos, a “likely story,” which does not claim absolute certainty but reveals, through reason and image, how the soul may orient itself by the eternal pattern that underlies all change.
The present essay will unfold the “Timaeus” in stages, treating it not as a relic entombed in antiquity but as a living text whose questions still shape the highest aims of philosophy.
Today marks Part I. The course of inquiry will follow the dialogue itself: first the dramatic frame of the discourse, then the distinction between being and becoming, then the vision of the divine craftsman. From there we shall turn to the role of the receptacle, the generation of the world-soul, the constitution of the elements, the nature of time, the relation of intellect and necessity, and finally the account of man as a microcosm within the whole.2/ The “Timaeus” opens as a sequel, carrying forward the conversation of Plato’s most celebrated work, the “Republic.” On the previous day Socrates had described the ideal city, its classes and laws, its guardians and its rulers. Yet he remains unsatisfied. What has been drawn in speech remains fixed, like painted figures that suggest life but lack motion. He therefore asks his companions to animate the city, to set it in action, and to show how it would contend with other states.
The company assembled is carefully chosen. Critias, claiming descent from Solon, recalls the Egyptian priest who told Solon that the Greeks were like children, forgetful of their own antiquity, and who related the tale of Atlantis, the mighty island that once warred with Athens. Hermocrates, the Syracusan general, embodies the statesman’s concern with power and strategy, while Timaeus of Locri represents the philosopher, a man steeped in Pythagorean mysticism, versed in number, harmony, and astronomy. Plato gathers them with deliberate purpose, forming a hierarchy of voices: the politician recalling the lessons of history, the general knowing the nature of conflict, and the philosopher alone capable of speaking of the cosmos.
Even the absence of a fourth guest is meaningful. On the surface it lends the dialogue dramatic realism, as if Plato wished to assure posterity that this was a genuine exchange. More deeply, the triad itself is symbolic: three voices suffice to reflect politics, war, and philosophy, yet their very incompleteness points to the truth that ultimate questions cannot be resolved by the many, but only by the few, and above all by the philosopher, who must bear the greatest burden. It is difficult not to hear in this structure an echo of what Georges Dumézil would later identify as the Indo-European tripartite order of sovereignty, arms, and sacred wisdom, but that is a subject for another section of this essay.
Socrates begins by rehearsing the “Republic” in miniature, repeating its themes so that the new inquiry can build upon them. The cosmos, he implies, is the greatest of all cities, and just as the soul is the microcosm of the city, the city is the microcosm of the universe. The order of man and the order of nature are linked, and philosophy must grasp both if it is to be complete.
It is Critias who first responds, offering the tale of Atlantis as told to Solon by the Egyptian priests. The point, however, is not Atlantis itself but Athens, presented not merely as an ideal city in speech but as a historical reality, noble in its victory over barbaric wealth and hubris. Yet Critias does not continue the tale to its end. He yields the floor to Timaeus, for the story of the cosmos must precede the story of a city. The defeat of Atlantis will belong to another dialogue, the unfinished “Critias.” In the “Timaeus,” the stage is cleared for a higher task: to speak of the beginning of the universe itself.
The dramatic frame is not a mere literary device but shows that politics without cosmology is partial and incomplete. The city must be ordered by the same principles that govern the heavens, and the soul must imitate the harmony of the whole. By setting the scene in this way Plato reminds us that philosophy must not stop with the affairs of men. It must look upward to the order of being itself, for only in the contemplation of that order can the city, the soul, and the world be brought into concord, and it is precisely this order that Plato next sets forth in his distinction between being and becoming.
Sep 5 • 5 tweets • 8 min read
1/ In 2011, Patrick Buchanan released Suicide of a Superpower: Will America Survive to 2025? The title was not rhetorical flourish but a forecast of things to come, a warning that the American nation’s unraveling had entered an advanced stage. Now that the year has arrived, his grim prophecy confronts us with full force. What he described as a looming possibility has hardened into a palpable reality that we all see, feel, and experience every day. The passing of White America is no longer a specter on the horizon but a condition of reality unfolding before our very eyes.
Buchanan wrote of a nation that had exchanged demographic homogeneity for balkanization. The old America, rooted in European descent, language, and inherited folkways, was set upon another course by the mid-1960s. Immigration laws were rewritten, cultural norms overturned, and political elites began to preach the virtue of dispossession as if it were a moral necessity. By the twenty-first century, the historic majority was told to welcome its reduction to minority status. Buchanan named this sickness for what it was: ethnomasochism, the strange delight in one’s own eclipse.
When President Bill Clinton addressed the graduates of Portland State University in 1998 and announced that their children would inhabit a nation with no majority people, the students applauded. A generation trained to rejoice in its own erasure gave proof that America was not merely declining by accident but dying by design.2/ At the heart of Buchanan’s warning lies the demographic collapse of the American nation. In the chapters “The End of White America” and “Demographic Winter,” he traces the dual catastrophe of declining White fertility and the relentless surge of non-White immigration. What he foresaw is now evident: replacement is not a theory but a measurable fact. The birthrates of European-descended Americans have fallen below replacement, while the gates have remained open to millions from the global South. The transformation, once projected for mid-century, is already visible in every major city and in much of the countryside besides.
This crisis cannot be explained by modernity alone, for secular and industrial societies in the past continued to grow. The deeper cause lies in a culture that has exalted individualism, consumption, and careerism above continuity and life. A generation that should have raised families instead pursued hedonistic self-fulfillment, leaving the future to the least fit. In White nations, this internal weakness has been coupled with an external policy of engineered replacement. Immigration laws after 1965 deliberately dismantled the ethnic character of the United States, turning homogeneity into a crime and diversity into a civic religion.
The result is a nation increasingly unrecognizable to its founders. Communities that once lived in trust now live in suspicion. Public life, once shaped by a shared European inheritance, is fractured into a contest of groups demanding spoils. The old American center has not merely weakened, it has been dissolved. Buchanan’s prediction has proven correct: a people that abandons its demographic foundations abandons its future.
Sep 4 • 8 tweets • 11 min read
1/ The American nation forgets its founders and calls it progress. Andrew Fraser’s “The WASP Question” is not an elegy but an exploration of decline, revealing how a people traded blood and memory for abstraction and became strangers in the ruins of their own homelands. 2/ What became of the founding people of America? Not the mythic immigrant multitude praised in modern textbooks, but the English stock that planted the first parishes, drafted the earliest colonial charters, fought the Indian wars, and declared independence in their own tongue and on their own terms. In “The WASP Question” Andrew Fraser asks with sober clarity why the Anglo-Saxon Protestant, once master of the institutions he created, now moves through their remnants as though he were only a guest.
This is a book about displacement, not merely political or social, but spiritual. It recounts the fall of a people who surrendered their ancestral memory to construct a universal republic, only to find themselves despised by the very order they had summoned into being. “Even in their own eyes,” Fraser observes, “WASPs now constitute little more than a demographic abstraction altogether devoid of the soul and the substance of a serious people.”
The origin of this decline, he argues, lies in the decision to exchange ethno-religious identity for constitutional idealism. The Founders, overwhelmingly Anglo-Protestant, raised up a civic faith in place of the older bond of blood and church. What had once been a concrete and embodied culture was reduced to an abstract doctrine of rights. A people rooted in land, lineage, and liturgy transformed themselves into apostles of a borderless creed. The commonwealth yielded to the marketplace, the Protestant conscience dissolved into global moralism, and the descendants of the founders became strangers to themselves.
Fraser does not call for a shallow political restoration. His horizon is deeper: palingenesis, a rebirth through memory. What he envisions is not the restoration of the American Republic, but the resurrection of the Anglo-Saxon spirit that preceded it, tribal, Christian, and conscious of itself.
This review will unfold in that spirit. It will trace Fraser’s account of WASP decline from the upheavals of the Reformation and the Revolution to the rise of managerial liberalism. It will consider his critique of civic nationalism, his theological reflections, and his call for a new aristocracy of memory. And it will weigh his vision not as lament, but as a possible path toward ancestral return in an age that no longer knows its own face.
Aug 25 • 5 tweets • 9 min read
1/ For generations, men far greater than I have sought to name the source of the West’s supremacy. In its essence, the answer is the uniqueness of the European peoples. Wherever European man has set foot, he has transformed the world, shaping wilderness into cities, tribes into nations, and myth into history.
No less have men sought to explain why the West now declines. The truth is equally plain to anyone who still possesses the capacity for honest thought. Europeans are being displaced in their own homelands. Civilizations are not sustained by slogans or institutions alone. They are carried by blood, by the living continuity of a people. When that people dwindles, society corrodes, and when it is replaced, the civilization ceases to exist.
The men of old knew this instinctively, for they lived beneath the eyes of their ancestors. A name was not a casual designation but a sacred burden, a banner of memory carried forward through time. To disgrace one’s line was to wound one’s very being; to ennoble it was to prove oneself the spearpoint of descent, the flowering of all that had gone before. Each generation stood within this chain, compelled to honor what had been received, yet also pressed by the desire to surpass it. In this there arose a tension deeper than philosophy, a law inscribed in blood itself: the obligation to remain a son of the clan, and the longing to stand apart as a man whose name would echo after his death.
It was from this tension that Europe drew her distinction among civilizations. In India, men were bound within castes where greatness meant the perfection of a role already fixed, conformity raised to a principle of eternity. In China, the weight of Confucian propriety pressed the individual into the service of family and empire until personality itself became a shadow cast by hierarchy. In Japan, courage and discipline were exalted in the figure of the samurai, but his nobility ended in self-extinction before his lord; he could die with beauty, but he died faceless, and no sagas were sung of him.
Europe alone preserved another order, in which the individual did not vanish into the collective but rose above it as its crown. Homer sang not of a people dissolved into anonymity but of Achilles, whose wrath bent the fate of armies. The tragedians of Athens carried this further, showing how the choices of a single king could reverberate through time and overturn the destinies of nations. And in the North, the sagas of Iceland and the legends of the Volsungs gave immortality to men who defied both kin and fate, standing forth from the tribe with such force that their names became indistinguishable from the destiny of their people. 2/ To strive for renown was never simply to indulge pride or to advance the clan by cunning calculation. It was to place oneself before the eyes of gods and men, to gamble one’s life against time itself. When a man distinguished himself, his triumphs magnified the strength of his kin and secured the continuation of the tribe. Women sought the one whose name resounded louder than the rest, for in him they saw not merely a protector but the very fountain of life renewed. Yet this striving cannot be reduced to what modern science calls reproductive fitness, for the heroic impulse often cut against survival.
Achilles, when offered the choice between a long but obscure life and a short life crowned by glory, chose the latter. His renown would outlive him, and that permanence was of greater worth than longevity. The Norse sagas are filled with men who fought duels or avenged insults that to modern eyes seem trivial, willingly spilling blood and forfeiting safety to preserve honor. These were not careful strategies of adaptation but wagers with eternity itself. They reveal a people who valued the story of their lives more than the continuation of their breath.
And the men themselves spoke in these terms. They did not justify their actions as prudent or useful but as worthy of remembrance. In the Hellenic world the word was kleos, glory or fame, the song that endures after death. In the North it was lof, the praise that lives in speech and memory. Both terms point to the same truth: that life only achieves permanence when it is preserved in the words of others, when it becomes part of the story. A man might perish, but if he had lived greatly his name could not die.
This was the consciousness of saga, the awareness that life itself is speech. The Old Norse saga means “that which is spoken,” the tale that carries a life across generations. In Greek thought, the parallel is logos, a word that means not only “speech” but also “gathering,” “reckoning,” and “order.” In Heraclitus, logos names the hidden harmony of the world, the measure by which all things are disclosed. To live for saga, then, is to live toward speech, to act in such a way that one’s life can be said, that it may be gathered into the memory of the people and aligned with the order of things.
The hero thus became the visible form of the tribe’s continuity. He was not merely a vessel of descent but a figure who gave shape and brilliance to descent. His deeds, once spoken, became part of the people’s hoard of memory. Each saga, whether of Achilles or Sigurd or Beowulf, was a fragment of eternity wrested from the flow of time: to live in such a way was to accept death, yet to defy oblivion.
Aug 24 • 7 tweets • 9 min read
1/ There is no greater lie than the illusion of Left versus Right.
The illusion begins not with eternal truths of politics but with the intellectual vanity of the Enlightenment. In the eighteenth century, European thinkers proclaimed that mankind could be remade through reason, that centuries of tradition could be overturned by argument, that the fabric of authority woven from throne and altar could be dissolved by pamphlets and constitutions. The Enlightenment was not only a philosophical movement but a political wager: that society could be rationalized, equalized, and universalized, that men could be abstracted from their peoples and treated as identical units of an ideal humanity.
This experiment culminated in the French Revolution, when the old order was swept aside in the name of “liberty, equality, and fraternity.” It was in this moment of destruction that the terms Left and Right were born, not as metaphysical categories but as a matter of physical seating. Deputies who favored revolution sat on the left side of the National Assembly, while those who wished to preserve the monarchy sat on the right. From this trivial arrangement a new political cosmology was fabricated, as if the placement of men in a hall determined the destiny of nations.
The categories hardened in rhetoric even as their meaning shifted. What had been a geographical convenience became a moral code. The Left was said to embody progress, the Right to embody reaction. The Enlightenment dream of remaking mankind was projected onto the chamber itself, where sides of the room now stood for sides of history. In truth, what was born was not a science of politics but a myth of polarity, a binary that would mask the deeper realities of descent and power, and in time serve as an instrument to strip Whites of their identity while cloaking their dispossession in the language of ideology.
2/ From their accidental birth, the categories of Left and Right never held firm. They stretched and twisted with each generation until the terms no longer marked consistent principles but only shifting alignments of power. What counted as liberal in one century became conservative in the next; what was once condemned as reactionary later reappeared as reform. The binary proved incapable of anchoring political reality because it was never founded on anything more substantial than expedience.
The nineteenth century revealed this mutability with merciless clarity. Liberals who once defended property and the free market against aristocratic privilege became, in time, the advocates of universal suffrage and redistribution. Conservatives who once upheld hierarchy and tradition soon made their peace with industrial capitalism, defending not throne and altar but profit and parliament. By the twentieth century, entire regimes could switch places on the spectrum without altering their essential methods: communism and fascism both claimed to be revolutionary, both were accused of reaction, both were denounced as Left or Right depending only on who wielded the label.
The present age is no different. Causes that only yesterday were the banners of progress, such as same-sex marriage, unrestricted speech, and suspicion of concentrated wealth, have been abandoned by progressives themselves, who now demand censorship and celebrate corporate power as long as it drapes itself in the language of diversity. Conservatives, once defenders of religion and restraint, now defend pornography as free expression and global finance as the essence of liberty. That the same terms are used to describe such shifting positions is proof enough that Left and Right are not realities but symbols, empty vessels into which elites pour whatever serves their interests, while the deeper facts of ancestry and peoplehood are excluded from consideration.
Aug 22 • 4 tweets • 6 min read
1/ Equality is death, for where difference is erased, meaning itself perishes.
No idea has been more influential, and more ruinous for the modern West, than the belief in equality. It has reordered our institutions, rewritten our laws, and redefined the very meaning of justice. Enshrined as the highest moral principle, it now functions not as a policy aim but as a sacred imperative: untouchable, unquestionable, and enforced with the zeal of a political theology. Every major political tradition, whether liberal, social-democratic, or post-Marxist, proceeds from the assumption that inequality is inherently unjust and that the equalization of man is not only desirable but morally necessary.
Yet the civilization which has most ardently embraced this principle has not entered a golden age. It has entered a state of civilizational fatigue, demographic decline, and spiritual exhaustion. The attempt to engineer sameness across all domains of life has not led to harmony but to disorder; not to justice, but to inversion; not to liberation, but to rootlessness and despair.
The theoretical edifice of egalitarianism rests on a fundamental misreading of man’s nature and a willful abstraction from the biological, ancestral, and cultural structures upon which civilization rests. The modern state, in its liberal-democratic form, no longer merely tolerates this abstraction; it now demands that all meaningful distinctions between individuals, sexes, classes, races, and peoples be treated as morally inadmissible. From this moral axiom emerges the categorical imperative to eliminate all disparities in outcome, and to interpret their persistence as proof of oppression or injustice. Every form of advantage is reduced to illegitimate privilege, and every manifestation of excellence is viewed with suspicion, as if nature itself were guilty of prejudice.2/ Under such a regime, the distinction between the natural and the artificial is deliberately collapsed. The unequal distribution of capacity, intelligence, beauty, and virtue is no longer accepted as a fact of life but condemned as an artifact of discrimination. The solution, invariably, is coercive intervention: through forced integration, racial preferences, wealth redistribution, speech regulation, and ideological education. These measures are not justified as prudent corrections. They are demanded as acts of moral restitution, enforced without limit or reciprocal obligation.
Yet such policies do not abolish privilege. They merely reassign it. Where once privilege was the earned result of achievement, sacrifice, or inherited responsibility, it is now redistributed on the basis of grievance, victimhood, or numerical imbalance. The result is a political order in which those who build are punished, those who destroy are protected, and those who rule do so by moral manipulation rather than merit or service. The civilization is hollowed out from within. Its foundational stock is disinherited, its values inverted, its future surrendered. This is not a failure of egalitarianism. It is the fulfillment of its logic, which operates less as a political philosophy than as a death cult, ritually denying form, abolishing rank, and sanctifying the indistinct until nothing remains worth preserving.
What emerges from this inversion is not merely a disordered society, but a metaphysically broken one. For equality, when treated as a transcendent value, does not merely reorder politics. It redefines the structure of meaning itself. All meaning is rooted in difference. What is identical cannot be significant. What is indistinguishable cannot be valuable. To equalize is to erase form; and to erase form is to annul the conditions of significance. In every civilization worthy of the name, meaning was cultivated through hierarchy, orientation, and limit. Whether in ritual, in art, or in law, the affirmation of order presupposed a recognition of rank. The noble was higher than the base. The beautiful was higher than the grotesque. The eternal was higher than the contingent. The modern mind, in refusing to judge, refuses also to uphold. And what it refuses to uphold, it slowly forgets.
Aug 20 • 5 tweets • 11 min read
1/ Aristotle, Antipater, and the Death of Alexander the Great
The exact cause of Alexander’s death in June of 323, in the palace of Nebuchadnezzar at Babylon, has been a matter of speculation for more than two millennia, a riddle that has haunted historians from antiquity to the present.
Speculation in the ancient sources ranges from fever and natural illness to poison of the most exotic sort, and the truth will never be known with certainty. Yet to understand the political climate of 324–323, one must look not only to the king’s orientalizing program and the fury it aroused among his men, but also to the powerful figures who stood to gain from his removal.
In this regard, the Antipater and Cassander connection cannot be ignored. Antipater, a stalwart of Philip II, Alexander’s father, a member of the noble house of Iolaus and long-serving guardian of the Argead dynasty, the royal line to which both Philip and Alexander belonged, was one of the key figures who secured Alexander’s succession after his father’s assassination in 336. He governed Europe as regent and as strategos, or general, throughout the Asian campaigns, ruling Macedon, Greece, and the League of Corinth in Alexander’s absence. From this position of immense power, he became both indispensable to the empire’s stability and a natural counterweight to the young king’s expanding vision in Asia.
Antipater was more than a caretaker of Philip’s legacy, he was its living embodiment. He had been present at the creation of the League of Corinth in 337, the confederation through which Philip bound the Greek cities to Macedonian hegemony, and it was Antipater who preserved its fragile equilibrium while Alexander pursued conquest abroad. He upheld Philip’s military system, ensuring that the machinery of the Macedonian state, its phalanx, its cavalry traditions, and its network of loyalist cities, remained intact through a decade of foreign war. He negotiated tirelessly with Athens, Sparta, and the other proud poleis, alternately cajoling, bribing, and threatening them into compliance. When revolts broke out, it was Antipater who raised armies and crushed resistance, reminding the Greeks that Macedonian supremacy was not merely the will of one king but the entrenched order of the age.
In his person Antipater represented continuity, a bridge between Philip’s hard-forged hegemony and Alexander’s world-spanning vision. To many in Macedon and Greece he was the guarantor of stability, the anchor of tradition, a statesman who stood for discipline and the old ways. His court at Pella, sober and conservative, embodied that ethos, a deliberate counterpoint to the glittering orientalized pageantry of Babylon. Between the two courts, the traditionalist Macedonian heartland and the hybrid experiment of the new empire, lay the fault line that would ultimately fracture Alexander’s legacy.
Antipater’s opposition was strengthened by his long-standing bond of xenia with Aristotle, that sacred institution of guest-friendship which bound men together across distance, time, and fortune. This was no casual acquaintance but a relationship sanctified by tradition, demanding loyalty, mutual aid, and an almost familial trust. The two maintained it through years of correspondence, and in Aristotle, Antipater found not only a friend but a kindred spirit.
The philosopher, who had once been entrusted with the shaping of Alexander’s mind in the quiet groves of Mieza, had ample cause to resent the king in his later years. As we have already discussed in relation to the fate of his nephew Callisthenes, the court historian whom Alexander himself had appointed, the resentment was personal as well as political. Callisthenes was no ordinary kinsman. He had been close to Aristotle from youth, almost a son rather than a nephew, and together they had worked to continue the Hellenica, a history of Greece conceived as a sequel to Thucydides. The bond of family was deepened by that of scholarship, the master and his kin joined in both blood and letters.
This made his fall all the more grievous. Callisthenes refused to abase himself in the Persian rite of proskynesis, the gesture of prostration before the king that blurred the line between man and god. Not long after, when the so-called Pages’ Conspiracy was uncovered among Alexander’s attendants in 327, the historian was accused of complicity. Whether guilty or merely a convenient scapegoat, the result was the same. He was clapped in irons, chained like a criminal, and dragged before the Macedonian court.
Ancient reports vary, but none absolve Alexander of cruelty. Some say Callisthenes was kept in fetters for months, denied food until his body wasted away, rotting in filth and despair. Others whisper that he was stretched upon the rack, his joints torn from their sockets, or even crucified like a slave along the dusty roads of Bactria. However the end came, it was brutal, a calculated humiliation not only to the man himself but to his family and, above all, to his uncle. For Aristotle, the stain clung like blood.
As we have discussed previously, the insult cut deeper still when set against Aristotle’s older grievances with the Argead house. Decades before, Philip II had razed Aristotle’s native Stagira to the ground, scattering its people, enslaving its children, and erasing the city from the map. Though it would later be restored, the memory of its destruction lingered, and no restoration could ever wipe away the humiliation. To see his nephew shackled, starved, and tortured by Philip’s son was to reopen that wound, as if the cruelty of the father had returned in the son with redoubled force.
For Aristotle, the boy he had once taught Homer and ethics had become a tyrant, and the tyrant had murdered his kin. The family bond was dishonored, the city of his birth avenged only in ashes, and the balance of blood was set. It is no wonder that his sympathies inclined far more to Antipater’s stern Macedonian conservatism than to Alexander’s grandiose vision of fusing East and West into a single order.2/ The final crisis between Alexander and his Macedonians came at Opis in 324. There, on the banks of the Tigris, the king laid bare his designs for the future. Before the assembled army he announced the demobilization of more than ten thousand hardened veterans, men who had followed him from Chaeronea through Granicus, Issus, Gaugamela, and beyond the Hyphasis. At the same time he paraded thirty thousand Persian youths, the so-called epigonoi, the “successors,” drilled in the Macedonian style of arms and discipline. To the veterans this was no honor but a calculated humiliation. They heard in the word “successors” the quiet declaration that their places in the phalanx, and perhaps in the king’s favor, were already forfeit to Asiatics.
The mutiny was fierce, the air filled with angry cries that Alexander had forgotten the companions of his youth and preferred Persian boys to the blood of Macedonian men. Their rage was sharpened by betrayal. Only months before, at Susa, Alexander had solemnized the marriages of his Companions to Persian brides and legitimized the unions of thousands of ordinary soldiers with Asiatic women, even granting each man a wedding gift from the royal treasury. Now he dismissed those same veterans and ordered them back to Macedon under Craterus, while their wives and children were compelled to remain behind in the East. The men who had marched with him for two decades, from the plains of Greece to the Indus, were thus stripped not only of their honor but of their newly forged households, the very families Alexander himself had bound them to. The insult was profound: they were cast off, while the future of Macedon was to be carried forward by Persians.
Alexander, cold and unyielding, crushed their defiance. In a gesture meant to soothe, he proclaimed all his Macedonians syngeneis, “kinsmen,” borrowing a Persian courtly title and clothing it in Greek. Yet the words rang hollow. The veterans knew that their families were left behind, their marriages severed by royal decree, their bloodlines deliberately entwined with a people many of them despised. What they saw was not reconciliation but confirmation that their king had crossed irrevocably into the Persian world.
For Antipater in Pella, the scene at Opis was further proof of all he had feared. The men returning to Europe would carry bitter tales of betrayal, of wives and children abandoned, of a king who called Persians his kin and dishonored Macedonian blood. To the regent, loyal to Philip’s memory and the old order, Alexander’s orientalizing vision was not simply arrogance but apostasy, the willful destruction of Macedonian identity itself.
The men were cast aside, humiliated, and sent home under Craterus. Yet this dismissal was not merely a matter of logistics. I, and others, have speculated that Alexander’s intent was far more deliberate: Craterus was to return with seasoned men still loyal to him personally, and with their strength dislodge Antipater from his entrenched regency in Europe, perhaps even to remove him outright by force or assassination.
Here lay the real collision: Antipater’s traditionalist court at Pella, anchored in the memory of Philip and the iron discipline of the old Macedonian ways, set against Alexander’s orientalizing program in Babylon, with its orchestrated marriages at Susa, its proclamation of Persian kinship in Greek words, its thirty thousand successors drilled in the Macedonian style, and its vast utopian vision of a new Persian-Macedonian nobility that would dissolve the very order from which he had sprung. And in that collision, the intrigues of the next generation found their spark, in Antipater’s ambitious son Cassander, who would soon make his uneasy appearance in Babylon itself.
Cassander, raised at the Macedonian court in the same generation as Alexander but never of his inner circle, was cut from a different cloth than the companions who had marched with the king from boyhood. Ancient sources agree in painting him as ruthless, calculating, and consumed by ambition. At Babylon he appeared awkward and out of place in the glittering, half-Persian court. Plutarch preserves the telling detail that, when brought before Alexander, Cassander trembled and stammered under the king’s gaze, mocked by others for his lack of composure. The humiliation seared into him a lasting hatred of Alexander’s memory, a hatred that would shape the rest of his career.
Aug 19 • 4 tweets • 8 min read
1/ The Indo-European is a form of man, an order of existence. It is not merely a linguistic family, nor a paleontological curiosity to be catalogued among fossils and shards. It is the expression of a structure so primordial that it recurs wherever Europeans have turned their vision: in myth, in law, in philosophy, in the very anatomy of the body. To see this order clearly is to recover something of our own hidden measure.
The great discovery of Georges Dumézil was that the ancient Indo-European peoples, whether Vedic Indians, Romans, Norsemen, or Celts, conceived their cosmos and their societies according to a tripartite law. There were always three functions: a sacred sovereignty marked by wisdom and command; a martial estate defined by courage and force; and a third estate devoted to fertility, sustenance, and production. Kings, warriors, and cultivators; priests, knights, and herdsmen: different names, but the same trinity. This was no mere sociological pattern but metaphysics made flesh in custom and rite, a recognition that Being itself discloses itself in three irreducible modes.
The Indo-European inheritance, therefore, did not remain fixed in its earliest forms. Each people reinterpreted the triad according to its own genius, its inner daemon, the guiding power that shaped its destiny and gave its institutions their particular stamp.
Among the Aryans of India, the castes hardened into a rigid hierarchy, sanctified by the vast metaphysical speculations of the Brahmins. Among the Romans, the triad became a civic constitution, written into law and embodied in the dignity of magistrates and patricians. Among the Germanic peoples, the same order was carried forward with Odin, Tyr, and Thor as guardians of wisdom, of law, of battle, so that the sagas themselves preserved the old Indo-European measure.
As Europe took shape, the Indo-European inheritance was not merely preserved but transfigured. The land and its peoples impressed upon it a new style, so that it bore the character of European man himself: balance joined with inner dynamism. It was never sufficient to leave the three functions as rigid castes or fixed estates. European thought and European form sought instead to weave them together in living synthesis.
Even the very word “king” in the Germanic and Celtic tongues implied one who bore all three functions within himself. The sovereign was not priest alone, nor warrior alone, nor provider alone, but the living microcosm of the entire order. This instinct for synthesis, for gathering the manifold into a higher unity without dissolving the distinct, appears already in Homer and in Plato, and later shapes the Gothic cathedrals, the theology of Aquinas, and the Renaissance vision of man. Here harmony was never homogeneity, but the just proportion of distinct powers.
Thus the Indo-European bequest is no antiquarian relic but the very code of Europe’s being, a grammar of order that reappears whenever the continent rises to self-consciousness. To recover it is not to imitate dead forms but to awaken again to the structure that underlies both cosmos and man. The tripartite law is the architecture of reality itself, and Europe’s destiny has always been to discern, to articulate, and to live according to that measure.2/ If Indo-European society was ordered according to a tripartite law, it was because this law was already inscribed within the soul itself. Political forms are not arbitrary inventions, nor the product of mere expedience; they are projections outward of the inner constitution of man. The city is the soul writ large, the macrocosm, and the soul is the city in miniature, the microcosm.
Plato, in the “Republic,” gave the classical expression to this insight. He distinguished the logistikon or rational soul, the thumoeides or spirited soul, and the epithumētikon or appetitive soul. The rational seeks truth and order, the spirited seeks honor and victory, the appetitive seeks nourishment, pleasure, and increase. These are not random impulses but distinct strata of being, each with its own dignity and necessity. When Plato assigns rule to the rational, guardianship to the spirited, and service to the appetitive, he is not spinning a theory out of the aether but recognizing the deep affinity between psychic structure and civic order.
Later thought confirmed and expanded this recognition. The physiognomic schools of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, though now dismissed, recognized three primary body types that parallel the tripartition of the soul. The ectomorphic, cerebral, nervous type corresponds to the priestly and sovereign function: cool, withdrawn, dominated by the head. The mesomorphic, muscular, broad-shouldered type corresponds to the warrior function: vigorous, aggressive, predisposed to action. The endomorphic, round-bodied, digestive type corresponds to the third function: content with food, with plenty, with the enjoyment of life. These are not mere accidents of physiology but outward signatures of inner predominance. The body is a visible hieroglyph of the soul.
Nor does the correspondence end there. Within the organs of the body itself, the tripartition reappears. Wolfgang Schad, the German biologist and anthroposophist, distinguished three great systems in the mammalian organism: the nerve-sense system, the respiratory-circulatory system, and the metabolic-limb system. These correspond precisely to the three functions: the guiding sovereignty of the nerves and senses, the militant energy of the blood and breath, the productive labor of the stomach and limbs. Each system, like each estate, cannot exist without the others; yet in man they are balanced, so that no one system wholly dominates. This balance is unique to man, and it suggests that man himself is not merely another animal, but a microcosm that gathers the whole order of nature into his own frame.
Thus the tripartite law is not only a principle of society, but of psychology, of physiology, of anatomy. Man himself is the first testimony to its truth.
Aug 15 • 5 tweets • 5 min read
1/ The crisis of Western civilization is two-fold: a crisis of nationalism and of manhood.
Those who would dissolve the nations of Europe know this truth instinctively, which is why they condemn both masculinity and nationalism as threats to be broken.
The bond between them is forged in nature itself. Nationalism is the love of one’s own, the unyielding loyalty to blood and kin over the claims of the stranger, and the readiness to defend them with word and with steel. It is the instinct to stand with one’s people when the line is drawn. And when the hour comes to fight for the tribe, it is men who must step forward, for that duty has always been theirs.
Men fight because the defense of their own is an extension of themselves. Nature has fitted them for this role, granting the strength, endurance, and aggression necessary for combat, while women bear the far greater burden of sustaining life itself. A people can endure the loss of many men, but the loss of its women imperils its very future.
For this reason, it has always been the task of men to stand between danger and those they protect. Without this instinct, nations perish; with it, they endure against every enemy. And when that instinct is erased, the end follows swiftly.
2/ The enemies of mankind know this law: to destroy a nation, they must first destroy its men.
Masculinity is branded as toxic, courage as aggression, pride as vanity, and loyalty as a dangerous relic of less “enlightened” times.
The very nature of manhood is blurred by the exaltation of sexual confusion, by a culture that prizes androgyny and feminization, that traps society in the stifling confines of the literal longhouse, and wipes away all distinct gender roles.
Boys are medicated and “educated” into passivity, their natural spiritedness pathologized. Men are told their strength is oppressive, their leadership unwelcome and branded misogynistic, their natural instincts suspect. A people that accepts such terms will surrender before the battle has even begun, and that is the purpose of the campaign.
The ancients named the force that animates defense and loyalty. In “The Republic,” Plato described the tripartite soul: reason, which seeks truth and understanding; desire, which seeks survival and satisfaction, the base forms of life; and thumos, the spirited element that resides in the chest, which seeks honor and the defense of what is one’s own. Thumos is the inner fire that rises against insult, refuses humiliation, and demands that loyalty be repaid in kind.
Every man is ruled by one of these parts. Where reason governs, he orders both spirit and appetite toward higher ends, seeking wisdom and justice. Where thumos governs, he becomes a man of action, loyal, passionate, and willing to hazard himself for pride or principle. Where desire governs, he becomes a man of appetite, a bourgeois man, concerned only with comfort, wealth, safety, and all things material, biological, and immediate, and easily cowed when those are threatened.
The same law applies to the city and the nation. A people ruled by reason will produce statesmen, philosophers, and judges. A people ruled by thumos will produce warriors, heroes, and defenders of the common honor. A people ruled by desire will produce merchants and clients, a commercial order that fears hardship more than dishonor.
The highest order is found where reason and thumos are joined, each guiding and strengthening the other, lifting a people above the baseness of mere desire toward the pursuit of what is noble and lasting.
The fate of every political order depends on which part of the soul it cultivates in its citizens.
Our ancestors understood this, which is why the old training of youth, whether in the Spartan agoge, the Roman mos maiorum, or the medieval code of chivalry, sought to elevate spirit and discipline appetite. Where that training is lost, men decay into consumers, and nations into markets. In such a state, collapse is not a possibility but an inevitability.
Aug 14 • 5 tweets • 9 min read
1/ “A decline in courage may be the most striking feature which an outside observer notices in the West in our days.”
— Aleksandr Solzhenitsyn
The twentieth century drove the peoples of Europe and their kindred across the ocean to the edge of civilizational ruin. Two world wars, revolutions, and ideological convulsions shattered empires and disfigured the moral order that had sustained the West for centuries. By mid-century, an alien creed, conceived in the fevered minds of émigré revolutionaries, had seized half of Europe and cast much of the White world beneath the shadow of the gulag and the mass grave.
From this maelstrom emerged Aleksandr Solzhenitsyn, soldier of the Red Army, inmate of the Soviet prison archipelago, and unflinching witness to the system’s crimes. His life traced the arc of his nation’s ordeal, from youthful service to disillusionment, from imprisonment to moral defiance, and finally into exile. By the 1970s, he had become the foremost voice of those who had endured the full weight of Communism, carrying that testimony into the heart of the West. In a sequence of speeches later gathered as Warning to the West, he spoke not as a partisan of Cold War maneuvering but as a moral witness to truths that transcended borders and decades.
To audiences still secure in their homelands, he spoke of dangers they could scarcely imagine. The West of his day remained composed of coherent nations, with a commanding White majority and a cultural confidence formed by centuries of civilizational achievement. Yet he perceived, even then, the same sickness that had once felled Russia taking root in the free world: a loss of will, a retreat from truth, and a readiness to appease the very forces that sought its undoing.
The empire he denounced has collapsed, yet the malady he diagnosed endures, its banner merely changed. Where class once served as the revolutionary rallying cry, race now fills that role. The objective remains the same: to dissolve the particular inheritance of the West, to estrange its peoples from their own past, and to reduce them to a formless, compliant mass.2/ Among the recurring themes in Solzhenitsyn’s speeches was his contempt for those who sought to purchase peace with the currency of concession. In the 1970s, this meant Western statesmen who posed as guardians of liberty while clasping hands with the very power that sought its destruction. They signed treaties whose terms the Soviet Union ignored before the ink had dried. They dispatched aid to a regime that repaid generosity with contempt, just as earlier relief efforts during Russia’s famine years had been recast by Soviet propaganda as acts of foreign espionage. Such leaders, Solzhenitsyn observed, mistook vanity for statesmanship, polishing their prestige at home while granting material advantage to their enemies abroad.
The lesson was clear: revolutionary regimes respect only firmness and hold in contempt those who yield. This truth has not altered in the decades since. Today the enemy no longer wears the red star, yet the pattern remains. The official, mainstream Right in the West, entrusted by its supporters to resist the radicalism of the Left, instead accepts the ideological premises of its opponents. It proclaims devotion to “equality” and “diversity,” surrenders moral ground on immigration and identity, and condemns White racial consciousness while defending or celebrating every other form of ethnocentrism. It opposes border walls at home yet votes to protect the frontiers of distant states. It speaks reverently of Martin Luther King and affirms the political myths that erode its own foundation.
In doing so, it signals not magnanimity but surrender. Like the negotiators of détente, it mistakes capitulation for diplomacy. Its leaders imagine that by showing goodwill toward those who seek their ruin, they will earn restraint in return. Yet the Left offers no such reciprocity. It does not purge its most radical voices. It does not temper the stream of anti-White invective that flows from its media organs. It does not respect the limits its opponents impose on themselves. It exploits every retreat as proof of weakness and as an invitation to press further.
Solzhenitsyn recalled Lenin’s grim jest that the bourgeoisie would sell the rope for its own hanging. The observation remains apt. In our time, the rope is woven from resolutions condemning “extremism,” from legislative bargains that weaken national sovereignty, and from the moral vocabulary of our adversaries repeated faithfully by those who call themselves conservative. It is sold cheaply, in great quantity, and the buyer has not changed.
Aug 14 • 5 tweets • 8 min read
1/ Eugenics is the science of shaping tomorrow's civilization by the wisdom of today.
Every civilization that has endured beyond the fleeting span of a dynasty has, in some form, governed the quality of its stock. In antiquity, this was not a subject for debate but an instinctive practice. It was ingrained in the order of aristocratic endogamy, the rigidity of caste, and the quiet yet steadfast exclusion of the weak from the privileges of reproduction.
In the modern era, this instinct acquired a scientific vocabulary and a deliberate program under the name eugenics, a term coined by Francis Galton to describe the conscious improvement of a people’s hereditary qualities through selective breeding, the shaping of marriage patterns, and now, through the precise instruments of genetic science. Its antithesis, dysgenics, is the slow erosion of that same hereditary capital through the multiplication of the unfit and the gradual attrition of the capable. Between these two forces, there is no neutral ground. A society that fails to refine its stock is not simply idle; it is in decline.
This is not a matter of political ideology, but of iron biological law. Intelligence, health, fortitude of character, and physical beauty, no less than disease, vice, and folly, are transmitted in blood. When the reproduction of the incapable is subsidized, when the capable are burdened by taxation, discouraged by a hostile culture, or distracted by sterile pursuits, the superior strain will inevitably be displaced.2/ Karl Pearson, one of the early titans of statistical science, demonstrated with precision that a relatively small portion of fertile families is responsible for producing the overwhelming share of future generations. When fertility moves inversely with intelligence, as modern research confirms with correlations as high as minus 0.73, the genetic drift toward mediocrity and incapacity advances rapidly and becomes irreversible without deliberate correction.
This insight was later amplified by Richard Lynn, whose work further validates Pearson’s warning. Their combined conclusions highlight a fundamental biological truth: societies that fail to maintain genetic quality through rigorous selection will inevitably face decline. As the least capable reproduce in greater numbers, the genetic fabric of a society deteriorates, diminishing the intellectual and physical capacities of future generations.
Pearson’s findings were expanded upon by the architects of the classical eugenics movement, such as Charles Davenport and Madison Grant, who further emphasized the dangers of inaction. The moment natural selection is suspended without being replaced by a deliberate and rigorous process of selection, societal decline becomes the inevitable outcome. This is not a matter of political ideology; it is biological law. A society unwilling to improve its stock will not stagnate. It will decline, as the multiplication of the incapable erodes the strength of the capable.
Eugenics takes two essential forms, each indispensable to the enduring health of a civilization. Positive eugenics seeks to encourage reproduction among the intelligent, the healthy, and the disciplined. In times past, this found expression in the marriage alliances of able families, the honor granted to households of proven worth, inheritance laws designed to concentrate advantages in the most capable lines, and the cultural reinforcement of standards that linked status with the raising of numerous and able offspring.
In the modern world, positive eugenics can be advanced by policies that reward the childbirth of the educated and competent, by substantial tax incentives that ease the burdens of large and capable households, by the public veneration of motherhood and fatherhood among those who embody excellence, and by deliberately nurturing the expansion of family lines whose hereditary endowment promises to strengthen the whole body of the nation.
Negative eugenics, by contrast, seeks to limit or prevent reproduction among those afflicted with grave heritable defects, persistent criminality, profound cognitive impairment, and other conditions that weaken the collective stock.
In the past, this might have involved measures ranging from infanticide in the most ancient societies to marriage restrictions, selective separation in later ages, and, in certain instances, sterilization.
Today, with the vastly greater resources of genetic science, negative eugenics may be pursued through comprehensive genetic counseling, the careful screening of embryos before implantation, and the precise removal of disease-causing genes. Such measures not only spare future generations from preventable suffering but also preserve the integrity and vitality of the national stock.
Aug 13 • 4 tweets • 6 min read
1/ “Democracy is a form of mass neurosis.”
Anthony Mario Ludovici was born in London on January 8, 1882, into a society and a civilization already yielding to the democratic and egalitarian impulses that were to become the constant adversaries of his life, and the abiding bane of the West.
His name is now largely absent from public memory, yet in the first decades of the twentieth century he stood among the most cultivated and steadfast defenders of the old European order.
Author of more than fifty books, one of the first translators of Nietzsche into English, original philosopher, painter, critic, polemicist, and political writer, he combined the breadth of a Renaissance humanist with the precision of a strategist. His writings traversed politics, religion, aesthetics, anthropology, and the relations between the sexes, yet his central and immutable concern was the cultivation and preservation of the highest human types.2/ Ludovici’s intellectual formation was grounded in an unshakable acceptance of hierarchy as a law of nature. He held that political order is never an abstraction, but the outward form of a ruling type, composed of men whose lineage, discipline, and intelligence have prepared them for the burden of command.
Democracy, in his estimation, was a political superstition, built upon the mystical “divine right” of majorities, an arrangement by which authority must inevitably pass into the hands of the least capable and the least far-seeing. He acknowledged the masses for their worth as workers and as soldiers, yet denied that their counsel in the affairs of state could ever be set beside the judgment of a hereditary elite, bound in duty to the destiny of the nation. In such works as “The False Assumptions of Democracy” and “A Defence of Aristocracy,” he exposed with patient severity the processes by which the modern franchise degrades governance into bribery, manipulation, and the restless pursuit of transient popularity.
His critique reached beyond the province of political theory into the very foundations of civilization. For Ludovici, aristocracy was not a mere constitutional arrangement but a principle of selection that had operated across the centuries in every culture that rose to greatness. Those civilizations which attained the highest refinements of art, philosophy, and statecraft, including Egypt, Greece, Rome, the great cultures of Asia, and the Americas, were all distinguished by relative isolation, by endogamy among their ruling houses, and by a deliberate cultivation of their own kind.
He observed that Egyptians, Jews, Greeks, and Incas alike, at the height of their powers, had set firm barriers against foreign admixture, and that their elites, to preserve the integrity of type, often resorted to close inbreeding. In the modern world, cosmopolitanism has broken these barriers, dissolving not only the physical harmony of a people but the cultural cohesion upon which the edifice of high civilization rests.