Excited to watch this talk by @renee_bowen_lyn : a model of echo chambers in social networks and how they take way less "behavioral error" than you might have thought to get started. Image
Paper here if you want to follow along

…9-a-62cb3a1a-s-sites.googlegroups.com/site/tamararen…

2/ Image
Behind the scenes there's a sort of puzzle based on a "naive martingale intuition": if there's abundant data and you understand the information process you're seeing, then a Bayesian should converge to accurate beliefs.

Well, information is abundant so.... what gives?

3/ Image
To put the focus on kind of intuition and why it may fail, the model is a pure learning model. Renee says: "There's NO game, there's no optimization," etc. Which I like! Pure learning forces are interesting/challenging enough.

4/
Here are some key motivating empirical facts.

5/ Image
Here's a summary of what the theory will deliver about how these forces matter.

6/ Image
And here's the preview of results on polarization. Note that polarization and different groups "different sets of facts" is an important and old observation in political science, and one that has been very motivating to theorists Image
Big literature on this! Typically quite difficult to model network communication "well": realistically and tractably..... :) Image
The information model is totally canonical: common priors about a binary state, independent binary signals ("pieces of news") about it. Quality of news is q, probability that a piece of news is accurate. Image
A key aspect of their model which is a departure from a totally canonical setup is that some people are dogmatic, and only share news from one side. These are the "crazy uncles," political partisans, whatever you want to call them.
More detail: there's a network communication model, and people hear things from their friends. Some friends share everything they know, others share selectively. Of course, the martingale intuition applies! If I have correct beliefs about how my friends communicate, ...
even if some of them only share the right-leaning signal, my beliefs will be correct on average and, under abundant information, will converge to the truth.
These observations are independent of the details of how network communication works. In this paper, info flow is modeled very simply: you can just share the signal you got with your friends, and info doesn't flow farther than that. So it's one-step hard information.
The first set of results is essentially this: if people do not have accurate beliefs about how much information their friends have (the probability gamma they have signals), then learning can be wrong. Image
Here's something weird/cool -- out of a very simple (essentially single-agent) model of information processing you get this funky curve of how expected posterior beliefs depend on the quality of signals. (In a Bayesian model this curve should be flat at 1!) Image
Here d_A is the number of A-partisans (people who share only A news) and d_B the number of B-partisans (people who share only B news). I think n is the number of normal agents who share whatever they hear but have to check this.
Yep, that's what it is. The authors ask next - is this about small neighborhoods (i.e. small number of signals?)

Nope - with as many signals as you want, long-run beliefs can be messed up in the long run.

"Long run" = signals keep coming and people keep communicating this way. Image
Intermission: plug for a related very active social literature focusing on the effects of misspecification on learning outcomes. This paper develops some techniques based on KL divergence etc., an important set of tools for general misspec models

personal.psu.edu/yxi5014/papers… Image
Intermission over! "Now we get to the fun results on polarization, what we were interested in from the get go"
One basic polarization result: restrict attention to the normal agents (non-dogmatic) and consider the difference in long run beliefs.

Polarization is positive and in fact some normal agents are sure of the correct state of the world while others are sure of the opposite Image
This is a set of essentially independent single-agent learning problems, and just because of somewhat different learning environments (and some misspecification, meaning perceived gamma is not true gamma) you end up with extremely different long run beliefs.
They study how the situation can be remedied by introducing public information aggregators that publish summaries of MANY signals.

NERD TIME! They use Hoeffding's inequality (I think) for binomial signals to bound how much this helps and whether it can overpower polarization
The model so far has been driven, at a technical level, by wrong beliefs of gamma (probability that your friends have signals). The authors show that misperception of other aspects of your informational environment can also lead to similar forces - e.g. wrong beliefs about Image
quality of your friends' information.
Ok, that's a wrap! Super interesting paper. A few quick, personal reflections.

In 2012 Matt Jackson and I used the "different sets of facts" that different political sides had about the Iraq war (even 10 years after it was over) to motivate a related study.
Today, different communities having different realities is, if possible, even more salient and troubling. It's exciting to see different theoretical efforts that shed light on this.
This paper focuses on the ways that this arises simply due to different people being exposed to different streams of (social) information, which they don't understand perfectly.

One-step "hard information" sharing still results in big polarization.
... at least in the long run. To learn correctly from your imperfect friends, you need to understand them perfectly, even if everything else is in your favor. That is a powerful point, and establishes a benchmark for other studies of polarization.
END :)

• • •

Missing some Tweet in this thread? You can try to force a refresh
 

Keep Current with Ben Golub

Ben Golub Profile picture

Stay in touch and get notified when new unrolls are available from this author!

Read all threads

This Thread may be Removed Anytime!

PDF

Twitter may remove this content at anytime! Save it as PDF for later use!

Try unrolling a thread yourself!

how to unroll video
  1. Follow @ThreadReaderApp to mention us!

  2. From a Twitter thread mention us with a keyword "unroll"
@threadreaderapp unroll

Practice here first or read more on our help page!

More from @ben_golub

23 Jan
Ok, my own answer to @JSEllenberg's question.

Here are some important statements that come up in economics:

"Nice estimators are consistent even in complicated models."
"Nice financial markets are informationally efficient."

1/
"Nice markets have price equilibria."
"Nice games have Nash equilibria."

The way these ideas are taught to Ph.D. economists in any field, even in core courses, involve very explicitly and extensively ideas extending ones in basic analysis.

2/
In particular, those ideas are: convergence (in fairly big spaces), integration and probability/martingales, continuity and fixed points.

Though you could get across aspects of these ideas at a high school level, econ grad school doesn't do them that way.

3/
Read 7 tweets
23 Jan
One amusing feature of math classes at the master's level or above is that they almost take pride in not motivating the subject in external terms. For example, here's a page from a canonical textbook in algebraic geometry.

1/
This does a good job of reminding me of how Lecture 1 in such classes often felt, which is roughly, "The motivation for this class is fuck you. Let k be an arbitrary algebraically closed field. Now..."

Which was not a problem when I had my own motivations!

2/
At some point it stopped being enough. Incidentally, I don't think my economics courses were much better in the way of giving some great external motivation: I just found a cycle of self-reinforcing curiosity that kept me happily studying that subject.

3/
Read 9 tweets
4 Jan
If you think Bean Dad is a symptom of a broken media ecosystem (and it certainly is), may I remind you of the SUMMER OF 2001.

Also known as the SUMMER OF THE SHARK. Networks and print media were *obsessed* with shark attacks.

1/3 Image
An irony is that there were actually relatively few shark attacks, but all I remember playing in the gym on CNN was shark stuff.

I also remember thinking that if this is what they need to amplify, then surely we were due for something bad. (In fact, we were.)

2/3
The old guard media with their vast editorial discretion amplify all sorts of dumb garbage: random kidnapping, shark attack.

Bean Dad type stuff is at least weirder and somewhat more democratic.

So I think critics of new media should recalibrate a little bit on old media.

3/3
Read 5 tweets
4 Jan
Was grateful to share at an #ASSA2021 session today a bit on what I've learned in teaching an undergraduate course on the Economics of Networks.

A short thread to serve as a focal point for any follow-up conversation.

1/
What networks is about (very rough and probably somewhat idiosyncratic description)

2/
I taught several variants of an undergraduate elective on this exciting and growing area. It was at the applied math/econ/CS intersection -- sometimes cross-listed, sometimes just economics but open to (and taken by) applied math, CS, other students.

3/
Read 27 tweets
13 Dec 20
A polite, scathing, and comprehensive reply by @jasndoc and coauthors to the "ergodicity economics" of @ole_b_peters.

@NaturePhysics erred in not finding a referee who would ask these basic questions of the authors, but glad a reply is out there.

nature.com/articles/s4156…

1/
This thread gives my own gloss and expansion of some points Doctor et al. raise.

Peters and co think there is a hidden assumption of economic theory: specifically, they think expected utility theory secretly assumes a mathematical property called ergodicity.

This is false.

2/
Expected utility theory makes 4 assumptions, which are stated precisely and concisely in every graduate textbook. Ergodicity is not among them.

EU is not the kind of theory that can hide assumptions: it is like Newtonian mechanics, not like Freudian analysis.

3/
Read 15 tweets
12 Dec 20
Let me very briefly jot down some notes as I read...

Take a basic static input/output model, and suppose we don't worry about nonlinearities in static equilibrium (as Baqaee and Farhi very productively have done).

Then it's easy to know which shocks matter for welfare...

1/
Just look at the Domar weights of the sectors, which is a fancy way of saying their (suitably defined) size.

All the network stuff boils down to one easily-measured statistic.

Shocks matter more when they hit "bigger" sectors.

2/
Liu and Tsyvinski make the point that this won't hold in an economy with adjustment dynamics.

When input demands increase after a negative shock, it takes time to build/activate capacity.

3/
Read 11 tweets

Did Thread Reader help you today?

Support us! We are indie developers!


This site is made by just two indie developers on a laptop doing marketing, support and development! Read more about the story.

Become a Premium Member ($3/month or $30/year) and get exclusive features!

Become Premium

Too expensive? Make a small donation by buying us coffee ($5) or help with server cost ($10)

Donate via Paypal Become our Patreon

Thank you for your support!

Follow Us on Twitter!